Close Menu
  • Briefing
    • Review
  • Business
  • Essays & Editorial
    • Special Reports
  • Case Law
  • Life
  • Member Content
    • All Products
  • Contact Us
    • About Us
Facebook X (Twitter) Instagram
Facebook X (Twitter) Instagram LinkedIn
Nairobi Law MonthlyNairobi Law Monthly
Subscribe
  • Briefing
    • Review
  • Business
  • Essays & Editorial
    • Special Reports
  • Case Law
  • Life
  • Member Content
    • All Products
  • Contact Us
    • About Us
Nairobi Law MonthlyNairobi Law Monthly
Home»Archives»In defence of the Supreme Court
Archives

In defence of the Supreme Court

NLM writerBy NLM writerOctober 17, 2014Updated:March 22, 2023No Comments6 Mins Read
Facebook Twitter WhatsApp Telegram
Share
Facebook Twitter WhatsApp Telegram

The Nairobi Law Monthly September Edition

Aside from the Presidential Election Petition judge­ment, no finding by the Supreme Court has drawn criticism like the court’s finding in the Munya case that it has jurisdiction in electoral disputes other than presidential elections.

In the ruling on the application for stay of the judgment and order of the Court of Appeal, in Gatirau Peter Munya v Dickson Mwenda Kithinji & two Others, Supreme Court Application No. 5 of 2014; [2014] eKLR, the question before the judges was whether the Supreme Court had appellate jurisdiction in an election petition under Article 163(4) (a) of the Constitution, which confers on the court jurisdiction in appeals involving application and interpretation of the Constitution.

Justices Jackton Ojwang and Smokin Wanjala (the reason­ing was later endorsed by the full court) held that the central issue in the petition was whether the election was conducted in accordance with the principles of the Constitution, i.e. the provisions of Articles 81(e) and 86. The Court noted that the issues decided by the Court of Appeal, which were then fur­ther brought up on appeal to the Court, rested on constitu­tional interpretation.

The court observed at Para. 77 that: “…the Elections Act, and the Regulations there under, are normative derivatives of the principles embodied in Articles 81(e) and 86 of the Constitution, and that in interpreting them, a Court of law cannot disengage from the Constitution.”

Thus, the question whether an election was free and fair, under Article 81(e) and accurate, verifiable, secure, account­able, and transparent under Article 86 of the Constitution, would engage the Supreme Court’s jurisdiction to hear an appeal, under Article 163(4)(a) of the Constitution.

 

This ruling has attracted a barrage of criticisms in opin­ion pieces in newspapers and social media commentary. Theargument goes that the conduct of elections is regulated by statutory law i.e. the Elections Act and thus electoral dis­putes adjudication does not involve constitutional interpre­tation. In this piece I seek to show the genius of the Supreme Court’s reasoning and why the criticisms are founded on a failure to appreciate constitutional theory.

It is a virtual axiom in constitutional law that constitu­tional norms come in two prototypes: rules and standards/ principles. In her 1991 Harvard Law Review foreword, The Supreme Court 1991 Term—Foreword: The Justices of Rules and Standards, 106 Harvard Law Review 22, 121 (1992) Kathleen Sullivan memorably distinguished between a “jus­tice of rules” and a “justice of standards.” The accepted lore suggests that rules should be formulated to regulate recur­rent and frequent behaviors, whose contours can be defined with sufficient precision.

Rules therefore draw a sharp line between forbidden and permissible conduct. Rules rely on an ex ante perspective and are therefore considered the domain of the constitu­tional drafter. Standards, by contrast, should be employed to address complex, variegated, behaviors that require the weighing of multiple variables. Standards do not draw a sharp line between permissible and impermissible conduct. Standards tend to become concretized by means of specific rules.

Standards therefore often invoke delegation i.e. consti­tutional drafters instruct the legislature to bring the nor­mative intent into application in specific contexts. Thus constitutional rules, for instance, are said to be appropriate when certainty, uniformity, stability, and security are highly valued, whereas constitutional standards are seen as more appropriate when flexibility, individualization, open-end­edness, and dynamism are important.

This insight leads us to know that the provisions of Arti­cles 81 (General principles of the electoral system) and 86 (Obligations of the electoral commission during voting) of the Constitution are standards/principles and not rules. Parliament was empowered by Article 87 (1) of the Consti­tution to enact the enabling legislation and consequently, the Elections Act as well as the Rules and Regulations made there under came into being.

This helps us to delineate the question that the judges faced: what status to accord to interpretation of the rules (legislations) that have been enacted in furtherance of constitutional standards/principles? In a sense, by setting broad standards, the Constitution does not disengage from regulating a particular area, in this case the conduct of elec­tions.

Thus unlike with constitutional rules where there is no direct constitutional seepage into legislations and thus it is tenuous to argue that the constitution regulates that par­ticular subject, with constitutional standards the normative derivatives (legislations and subsidiary legislations) can be perceived as a continuation of constitutional regulation of a particular subject area.

The question that follows is how should judges interpret these legislations derived from constitutional standards/ principles? As Sullivan writes, “A justice of standards” prefers “to collapse decision making back into the direct application of the background principle or policy to a fact situation.” Building from the work of Sullivan, Aharon Barak notes in The Judge in a Democracy that “It is also important to distinguish between a statute based on rules and a stat­ute based on principles or standards. My approach is to give great weight to the intention of the legislature in interpret­ing a rule-based statute and great weight to the principles of the system in a more policy-oriented statute.

The reason for this approach is that under a statute es­tablishing rules, adjudication usually must draw a clear line between what the statute forbids and what it permits, and that distinction can be derived from legislative intent. By contrast, a statute that formulates principles or policies pre­scribes an ideal to be achieved. This ideal operates within the framework of the legal system, is shaped by it, and in turn influences it.”

In the end, the judges of the Supreme Court find support from some of the leading constitutional law theorists of our time (Laurence Tribe of Harvard Law School famously called Sullivan “the most extraordinary student I had ever had” while Richard Posner, a judge on the United States Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit and an authority on ju­risprudence has remarked that “if there were a Nobel prize for law, Barak would likely be among its early recipients”) that in interpreting legislations derived from constitutional standards/principles you are not to disengage from the Con­stitution.

The approach by Justice Ojwang and Smokin is sound in constitutional theory. This leads to the question, to borrow from C.F. Forsyth ‘In Danger for Their Talents’, are the Su­preme Court judges being criticized for proper appreciation of constitutional law ?.

The Nairobi Law Monthly September Edition

Email your news TIPS to Editor@nairobilawmonthly.com, and to advertise with us, call +254715061658 anytime of the day
Follow on Facebook Follow on X (Twitter) Follow on WhatsApp
Share. Facebook Twitter WhatsApp Telegram
NLM writer

The Nairobi Law Monthly September Edition

Related Posts

Distributed ledger tech: introducing hedera to the law

January 2, 2025

Technology investments for law firms in a post-COVID world

December 20, 2024

A moral inventory of oneself is king in recovering from alcoholism

May 1, 2023

New Safaricom CEO Dangerous for Workers’ Rights – COTU

February 28, 2023
Add A Comment

Comments are closed.

Download Latest Edition
Latest Posts
Briefing

Edgar Lungu’s final wish: Keep Hichilema away from my funeral

By Edwin Edgar MutugiJune 13, 2025
Briefing

Kayole police probe brutal killing of missing 11-year-old boy

By Edwin Edgar MutugiJune 13, 2025
Briefing

5-year-old girl dies after uncle throws her from balcony

By Edwin Edgar MutugiJune 13, 2025
Briefing

Post-mortem confirms torture in deaths of abducted Marakwet men

By Special CorrespondentJune 13, 2025
Briefing

Albert Ojwang’s death deepens rift between police and public

By Special CorrespondentJune 13, 2025
Facebook X (Twitter) Instagram LinkedIn
  • About Us
  • Member Content
  • Download Magazine
  • Contact Us
  • Privacy policy
© 2025 NairobiLawMonthly. Designed by Okii.

Type above and press Enter to search. Press Esc to cancel.